by Deena Weinstein and Michael A. Weinstein
1.
The revival of interest in Georg Simmel's thought that has occurred
in the English-speaking world since the early 1970s has brought to the
forefront of attention his contributions to cultural theory. Among
the commentators on Simmel's work Donald Levine (1971b) has integrated
Simmel's sociological studies and his philosophy of life around the dialectical
tension between "life" and "form;" Peter Lawrence (1976c) has provided
fresh translations of some of Simmel's major essays on culture and has
interpreted them in the context of the European civilization of his time;
and David Frisby (1981) has given a careful and rich account of Simmel's
intellectual spirit in light of contemporary hermeneutical categories.
The growing literature on Simmel's legacy is characterized by a welcome
tendency to consider his thought as a whole rather than to abstract from
it particular substantive or methodological contributions to sociological
inquiry, and to establish firmly that a concern with the problematicity
of modern culture is a unifying theme in his varied studies in philosophy,
aesthetics, and sociology. Contemporary Simmel scholarship offers
a sound basis for a further project of making some of the critical nuances
of his reflections on culture more precise. A more intensive examination
of key aspects of Simmel's cultural theory will not only provide a more
adequate picture of his thought, but will show its relevance to present
interpretations of culture.
2.
Current scholarship on Simmel is characterized by the legitimate aim
of placing his work in the context of the times in which it was written.
The approach of cultural history performs the salutary function of preventing
misplaced abstractions, but it often fails to grasp the significance of
a thinker for future generations. Any thinker is embedded in his
age, sharing with his contemporaries participation in distinctive discursive
formations which are intelligible both in terms of regnant social conditions
and the given level of cultural development in all of the phases of what
Simmel called, in the manner of Hegel, "spiritual life." However,
a thinker may also push beyond the confines of his era and anticipate the
problems which will preoccupy future reflection. Cultural history,
as it is practiced today, with the guiding intention of circumstantializing
a thinker, tends to neglect fruitful anticipations. Although it is
difficult both to make a thinker intelligible through his socio-cultural
circumstances and to show how he transcended them those two endeavors are
essential to a complete interpretation: history must strive to be adequate
to the temporal determinations of its object, but historiography rejoins
that the past is necessarily interpreted through present concerns.
3.
Lawrence (1976c:5) evinces the present direction of Simmel scholarship
when he writes that "Simmel is of interest as a representative, though
not always a typical representative, of both European culture before the
war of 1914-18 and of Wilhelminian Germany, though there is some opposition
between these two environmental forces." That understanding of Simmel
will tend to assimilate his thought to the special problems of German national
unification and the "cultural pessimism" which arose in Germany as the
Bismarckian formula of a thinly-disguised authoritarianism fell apart in
the years preceding World War I. Frisby (1981), indeed, makes Simmel
into the arch cultural pessimist by interpreting his spirit through the
free-floating retreatism of Robert Musil's Ulrich, "the man without qualities."
One need not deny that Simmel reacted painfully against "the First World
War which shattered the civilization he revered," or even that he sometimes
"displayed a characteristically German apathy towards contemporary politics."(Lawrence,
1976c:6) Much of Simmel's temperament is fully attuned to his period
and he acknowledges that fact in his late writings. However, among
his famous contemporaries such as Max Weber, Ferdinand Tönnies,
and Werner Sombart he was distinguished by a decided lack of nostalgia
and by a penetrating interest in emerging cultural phenomena, for example,
expressionism in art and pragmatism in philosophy, which casts doubt on
the picture of him as a man who could not summon the nerve to engage himself
in the great struggles of his time. If Simmel was a representative
of his epoch, both as German and as European, he was also a pathfinder
beyond it, most particularly in his late works on cultural theory, written
during World War I. As Georg Stauth and Bryan Turner (1988:16) note,
he "may be regarded as the first sociologist of post-modernity."
4.
The anticipations of future discourses in Simmel's work are articulated
with greatest precision in two of his most sensitive essays on cultural
theory, "The Crisis of Culture"(1917) and "The Conflict of Modern Culture"(1918).
In these writings Simmel emerges not as a cultural pessimist but as an
internal critic of modernism, anticipating in "The Crisis" the existentialism
of Martin Heidegger and in "The Conflict" contemporary "postmodernist"
perspectives. The following discussion will suggest that far from
suffering a failure of the will to engagement, Simmel in his later years
struggled deeply with the tensions of modern life, agonizing over them
and introjecting them into the core of his intellectual personality, and
seeking restlessly, though unsuccessfully, to overcome them. Simmel's
unwillingness or inability to take a stand in any of the movements of his
period or to found a school or a movement of his own do not bespeak, as
Frisby (1981) has it, the spirit of the "flâneur" or the impressionist,
who distances himself from the currents of life because he finds them too
multifarious and fluctuating to embrace in a consistent praxis; or, as
Lawrence (1976c) claims, a "characteristically German apathy." Instead,
the absence of partisan commitment in his intellectual life stems from
his placement of the problematicity of modernity in cultural conflict rather
than in economic, political, or social dynamics. Simmel traced the
crisis of modernity to an internal contradiction in culture and he strove
to discern signs of its possible reconciliation: he was not so much
"the man without qualities," the victim of a cultural pathology, as a Nietzschian
diagnostician and therapist seeking cultural health, an agonistic healer,
similar to his Spanish contemporary Unamuno.
5.
The following discussion will interpret "The Crisis of Culture" and
"The Conflict of Modern Culture" as parallel texts which address the same
phenomena of modernist culture - expressionism, post-metaphysical philosophy,
and post-Christian religiosity - in distinctively different ways.
"The Crisis," which is Simmel's most careful reflection on World War I,
interprets modernism in terms of the categories of his pre-War thinking,
recalling The Philosophy of Money and "The Metropolis and Mental Life"
but infusing those categories with a moral commitment leading out to the
existentialism of the post-War generation. Here Simmel's thought
is a bridge between the past and the immediate future, anticipating the
drive away from relativism and skepticism, and toward commitment that would
mark the inter-war period. "The Conflict," which is the most unique
and original work in Simmel's canon, pushes beyond the parameters of his
other writings, leaving off from the past and breaking entirely new ground
in its profound acknowledgment of the positivity of modernism and of its
essential failure: in this text the postmodernist discourse erupts.
In "The Crisis" Simmel is still a representative, though certainly not
a typical one, of his generation, though he is struggling painfully beyond
it. In "The Conflict" he is intellectually contemporaneous with our
own cultural situation, which gives us the privilege of understanding him
more fully than previous generations have been able to do.
The Exhaustion of Form
6.
"The Crisis of Culture," which is one of four essays collected in Simmel's
The War and Spiritual Decisions, has been generally ignored by commentators,
who find the notes of German nationalism that are sounded in his writings
on World War I to be uncharacteristic of his supposed cosmopolitan bias
and, perhaps, embarrassing. Lawrence (1976c), however, points out
that Simmel's "war enthusiasm" in "The Crisis" is "reasoned rather than
rabid." The essay, indeed, far from being a defense of the war spirit
is exemplary of Simmel's late cultural theory, framed in the context of
how the War affects the basic dialectical tensions in modern life.
Simmel shows in "The Crisis" how war reveals the presuppositions of peacetime
life in a "highly developed objective culture." His project is similar
to that of "The Metropolis and Mental Life"(Simmel, 1971c), in which he
traced the impact of the social form of the modern urban setting on individual
subjectivity, only now the form mediating cultural conflict is war.
The basic terms of that conflict are the same in both essays - the opposition
between objective and subjective culture - and recur to his masterwork
The Philosophy of Money (Simmel, 1978).
7.
Throughout his mature writings on culture, until the radical break
which he makes in "The Conflict," Simmel's fundamental description of modernity
is constituted by the tension between objective and subjective culture.
Working within the parameters of a naturalized Hegelian dialectic he defines
man as a being who objectifies his life in cultural forms, such as technology,
science, art, philosophy, and religion, which then demand that life conform
to their constraints and standards. Under ideal conditions the form-giving
activity of human life is able to appropriate its objectified creations
to fill out and enhance individual subjectivity, that is, the objective
culture of things serves the subjective culture of personal development.
In "The Crisis" Simmel(1976a:253) gives one of his best accounts of the
normative grounds of his cultural theory, arguing that "improvement of
the soul" is culturally achieved indirectly "by way of the intellectual
achievements of the species, the products of its history: knowledge,
life-styles, art, the state, a man's profession and experience of life
- these constitute the path of culture by which the subjective spirit returns
to itself in a higher, improved state." The foundation of Simmel's
cultural theory, then, is a triadic relation of form creation - objectivized
form - form appreciation, which functions ideally as a self-reinforcing
process through which human products come back to their creators to enrich
their lives. Simmel's descriptive analyses and his criticisms of
culture all trade off his normative ideal, showing the various ways in
which the reciprocal relation between the three moments of the fundamental
dialectic is broken in modern life.
8.
Had Simmel followed in Hegel's footsteps he would have endeavored to
show how the idealized dialectic of culture was the actual form of historical
development, but his deepest insight into human life was that the three
terms of the relation were inherently unbalanced. "The Crisis" culminates
Simmel's tragic sense of culture by bringing together his major arguments
about how the objective culture of modernity fails to serve the development
of the individual's personality. His radical claim is that the form-giving
activity tends to perfect its objective creations indefinitely through
differentiating them into autonomous cultural realms, which then are developed
according to their own inherent norms, and through generating ever more
intensive and extensive means to fulfill those norms. Meanwhile finite
individual subjectivity remains bound within its natural limits and becomes
progressively incapable of assimilating and appropriating the vast array
of cultural objects for its own perfection, and increasingly lost within
the jungle of means to the point at which it even loses sight of its native
goal. The crisis of an impoverished subjectivity confronting an overwhelming
objectivity is further exacerbated by the demands for service that each
realm of objective culture makes upon the individual spirit. Objective
culture, rather than serving the individual as it is supposed to in the
normative order, becomes the oppressive master of subjectivity in the actual
order of historical development. According to Simmel there is no
exit from this tragic predicament, which is grounded in the relation between
the indefinite perfectibility of objective culture and the inherent limits
of individual subjectivity: the highly developed objective culture
is in a state of "chronic crisis."
9.
The crisis of culture is enacted in a wrenching conflict within the
individual between the demands of objective culture and the struggle of
the self for its own expression of its life. The typical reaction
of subjectivity to chronic crisis is defensive and protective, that is,
to withdraw into a blasé attitude and to withhold commitment to
objective forms. The forms become exhausted of any meaning that they
might once have had for individual life and various pathologies appear
such as the equation of technological with cultural progress, overt covetousness
and craving for pleasure, and a desire for money that far exceeds the desire
for the things it can buy. Subjectivity trivializes itself as a defense
mechanism against the demands of the objective spirit, suffering from a
sense of futility rather than caring for its own enrichment. But
it also initiates more positive resistances such as war, which provides
an overriding end of group survival for life, and modernism, which in "The
Crisis" is a struggle for subjective culture in an age of exhausted forms.
War, for Simmel, is a temporary recovery of vitality and seriousness in
the persistent context of futility, and in the midst of its devastation
it may reveal to people how their values have been inverted by their resentment
against the overbearing demands of a fragmented objective culture.
Modernism, in contrast, is the extreme pathology of peacetime life, the
self-contradicted resistance of impoverished subjectivity, the flaring
up of an endemic cultural disease.
10.
Although Simmel does not use the term "modernism" he identifies "a
number of contemporary cultural phenomena" which would later be grouped
under that term. Indeed, he may be considered as one of the first to discover
the affinity between the various tendencies in diverse spheres of culture
that self-consciously attempt to rupture received conventions and to give
free play to immanent creative process. In "The Crisis" he interprets
such phenomena as futurist art, post-Christian religiosity, and post-metaphysical
philosophy, as responses to an environment of inherited cultural forms
which were "eroded and lacking in self-assurance." Modernism here
is the kind of creativity that occurs when there is "a passionate desire
for the expression of life, for which traditional forms are inadequate,
but for which no new forms have been devised, and which therefore seeks
pure expression in a negation of form, or in forms that are almost provocatively
abstruse."(Simmel,
1976a:257) The modernist impulse is described here negatively as
a spirit in a cultural interregnum that has lost allegiance to old models
but that is incapable of creating new ones. In light of its deprivation
it falls back upon itself and seeks to present itself "formless and naked."
But such an effort, according to Simmel(1976a:257), is doomed to failure
because the inner life can only be expressed "in forms which have their
own laws, purpose and stability arising from a degree of autonomy independent
of the spiritual dynamics which created them." Expressionism, which
tries to objectify psychological processes directly, ends in "a chaos of
fragmentary vestiges of form as a substitute for a form which is unified."
Futurism, which is Simmel's touchstone in "The Crisis," has created "prisons,"
not "pure expression."
11.
Post-Christian religiosity, which is best exemplified by a "formless
mysticism" through which the soul attempts to stand "naked" before its
God or to be "its own inmost metaphysical life not moulded by any forms
of faith whatever" is also traced by Simmel(1976a:259) to an "historical
moment when inner life can no longer be accommodated in the forms it has
occupied hitherto, and because it is unable to create other, adequate forms,
concludes that it must exist without any form at all." Simmel(1976a:258)
places the new piety, which would later resonate in the movement of process
theology, against the backdrop of pre-War culture, a "peaceful age of gradual
transitions, of hybrid forms, of that pleasant twilit zone where one can
indulge alternately even in mutually exclusive attitudes." He believes
that the War has ended that era of trivialized faith and ushered in a time
which "demands from each and every man a decision as to where he ultimately
stands." Anticipating Heidegger's (1962) notion of "resolute choice"
in Being and Time, Simmel hopes that the "resoluteness" that the Germans
have shown in the war effort "will also penetrate to this inmost area of
decision." Here Simmel adopts a decidedly existentialist outlook,
speaking of a "radical eruption of man's religious depths." He is
moving along the line of Karl Jaspers's existenz and Paul Tillich's "ultimate
concern," breaking out of the idea of religion as a cultural form without
falling prey to "formless mysticism." With his notion of radical
choice he is on the brink of discovering the forms of personal existence;
Heidegger's "existentials" and Jaspers's "ultimate situations," both of
which were forged in the effort to renew culture in the wake of its collapse
by revealing intimately real forms.
12.
The idea that modernism is a sign of what Heidegger called the interregnum
between gods, that it bespeaks the impotent yearning for new forms, carries
over into Simmel's discussion of post-metaphysical philosophy. Anticipating
Heidegger, Simmel suggests that the system of philosophy which has been
"elaborated since classical antiquity" is "beginning to become an empty
shell." Ideal antinomies such as free will and determinism, and absolute
and relative "no longer permit a clear decision to allocate any dubious
case definitely to the one concept or the other."(Simmel, 1976a:260)
There is a "demand for an as yet indefinable third possibility," because
"our resources for mastering reality by giving it intellectual expression
are no longer adequate to their task." The "philosophical instinct"
quests for "new forms, which as yet announce their arcane presence only
as intuition or perplexity, desire or clumsy gropings." In the inter-war
period there would be an effort throughout the West to engender those new
forms. Ludwig Wittgenstein would find in ordinary language the matrix
out of which philosophical abstractions escaped, Heidegger and later existential
phenomenologists would coordinate the classical antinomies in the category
of being-in-the-world, and the late Heidegger would make the daring attempt
to break through metaphysics altogether to the thought of Being itself.
None of those efforts has proven adequate to the traditional task of philosophy,
which, for Simmel, is to make reality intelligible, but they show that
the very problem he identified during the War would become the center of
philosophical reflection after it was over.
13.
The discussion of modernism in "The Crisis" is framed within the primal
understandings of the exhaustion of received cultural forms and of the
deprivation of subjective culture. Modernism, as a failed mediation
between form-creating activity and form appreciation, occupies a gap between
a past and a possible future culture, both of which provide a modicum of
satisfaction to the subjective demand for coherent personal development.
Although the essay concludes with an assertion that the "chronic crisis"
of highly developed objective culture cannot be reversed in the long run
Simmel(1976a:265) still nurses a hope that the tendency of such a culture
to "disintegrate into futility and paradox" will be recurrently arrested
by "the fundamental dynamic unity of life." He senses that
the "concept of life now seems to permeate a multitude of spheres and to
have begun to give, as it were, a more unified rhythm to their heartbeat."(Simmel,
1976a:263) Simmel here endows the form-giving activity of life with
its own meaningful integrity, its own inherent pre-intellectual and self-preservative
and self-renewing direction. The crisis of culture is the exhaustion
of form and its pathological manifestations are the currents of modernism
which attempt to dispense with form only because they are unable to create
it. Indeed, in "The Crisis" life and form are held in tension with
each other in a "process of interaction" - they are not antithetical forces,
but are defined reciprocally in terms of the polarity flux and fixed, each
one a necessary moment in the totality of the life process. The real
antithesis here, as it is through all of Simmel's work from The Philosophy
of Money until "The Conflict of Modern Culture," is between objective culture
(objectivized form) and subjective culture (form appreciation). Life
itself as form-giving activity is not problematized and, thus, can be dogmatized,
can remain a repository of hope for spontaneous renewal, encircling the
tragic opposition between the two cultures. In "The Conflict," however,
the ground shifts altogether and Simmel problematizes the relation of form-giving
activity to objectivized form, abandoning the last vestiges of his metaphysical
optimism and opening the door to postmodernist perspectives on culture.
He abandons the waiting game of the interregnum and enters the age of radically
contradicted life.
The Rebellion of Life
14.
Georg Simmel was the leading philosopher of life in Germany in his
generation, performing the function of assimilating the idealist tradition
into the ground of lived experience as it is seized directly from within
by a conscious finite self. Like his French contemporary, Henri Bergson,
with whom he is often compared, he philosophized from a vision of life's
structure which he achieved by a reflective review of the various human
activities, guided by his intuition of life's process. Far from taking
the pose of the detached ego who floats above life observing it indifferently
or of the flâneur who mingles in society but can take it or leave
it, he experienced to the depth all of the conflicts of his time.
He was acutely aware of the multiplicity and relativity of forms, but he
took each one of them seriously, pondering its internal meaning and its
relations to the others. He did not commit himself to the perfection
of any special form as a Weberian vocation, but concerned himself with
the problematicity of form itself: he was, on the contemplative side,
a cultural theorist, and, on the active side, a cultural critic.
He was a man of forms, not of form; a man of many qualities, not a man
without them. He understood and was loyal to a moral ideal of a culture
in which human beings express their lives in objects which return to them
to fortify their personal development, but he did not believe that this
ideal was capable of realization. Rather, in his review of life as
a whole he discovered irremediable paradoxes, ironies and contradictions.
15.
Simmel's vision of the dialectic of "form creation - objectivized form
- form appreciation" governed his entire mature intellectual development,
but he placed emphasis on different tensions within that dialectic over
time. Through the middle period of his career (1900-1910) he was
concerned with the conflict between objectivized form and form appreciation,
arguing that the objective culture of things had outrun the ability of
individuals to incorporate it into a satisfying subjective culture of personal
enrichment. He did not attend during this period to the moment of
form-giving life, leaving it as an unanalyzed ground and taking for granted
the "chronic crisis" of the highly developed objective modern culture.
In his late writings, however, a decisive shift in his focus occurs which
culminates in "The Conflict of Modern Culture." Whereas in the preceding
phase of his thought objectivized form was the protagonist overwhelming
form appreciation, which adopted a multitude of compensatory and defensive
measures to maintain some semblance of integrity, in his thought during
the War period the form-giving activity of life itself becomes the protagonist,
seeking to deconstruct objectivized form; to capture it, assert sovereignty
over it, and assimilate it into itself. Concern with subjective culture
drops out of his thinking, as though it had become anachronistic, and the
creative spirit confronts its products without the mediation of the appreciation
of culture: creative life seeks to become the self-sufficient appreciator
of itself, of its own creativity.
16.
Simmel began "The Crisis of Culture" by defining culture subjectively
as "the improvement of the soul" attained indirectly through "the intellectual
achievements of the species." The ground shifts decisively in "The
Conflict," which he initiates with the reflection that "we speak of culture
when the creative dynamism of life produces certain artefacts which provide
it with forms of expression and actualization, and which in their turn
absorb the constant flow of life, giving it form and content, scope and
order."(Simmel, 1976b:223) Culture is here primarily a product of
creative life, not an object of appreciative life. In light of this
new focus the site of the conflict of culture moves to an antagonism between
creativity and its creations. According to Simmel(1976b:223), form-giving
life produces objectivized forms which "have their own logic and laws,
their own significance and resilience arising from a certain degree of
detachment and independence vis-a-vis the spiritual dynamism which gave
them life." The independence of objectivized form from the life which
creates it is the root of cultural theory. The forms created by the
life process stand over against it, demanding that the process contain
itself within them. Life as creative activity, however, immediately
departs from them and seeks to engender new forms in which to express itself.
Objectivized form necessarily tends to become hostile to life, which constitutes
itself as cultural history by ceaselessly creating and abandoning a succession
of forms, none of which ever fully satisfies its restless and multifarious
drive for self-expression.
17.
The history of spiritual life, which is cultural history, does not
have, for Simmel, a formal unity or meaning, but it does reach an intelligible
crisis in the twentieth century. Until the present era the conflict
of culture had been fought out by the replacement of one form of meaning
by another, each one commanding obedience as an objective imperative and
then ceding to others after a struggle. But during the nineteenth
century a unique and far-reaching eruption occurred in modern culture:
life began to take itself as its own object of meaning, first in the thought
of such philosophers as Schopenhauer and Nietzsche (cf. Simmel, 1986),
and then in every region of culture; that is, life at last understood itself
as the generator of all of the forms to which it had pledged obedience
and could no longer tolerate subservience to objectivized form which it
knew to be its own product. By the twentieth century cultural movements
were in process that not only sought to replace exhausted forms with new
ones, but that rebelled against the submission to any objective demand:
"We are at present experiencing this new phase of the age-old struggle,
which is no longer the struggle of a new, life-imbued form against an old,
lifeless one, but the struggle against form itself, against the very principle
of form."(Simmel, 1976b:225) Simmel here breaks through the confines
of the "cultural pessimism" of much of his generation. He no longer
interprets modern history through the exhaustion of form but has discovered
the rebellion of life, toward which he experiences a deep ambivalence.
Indeed, Simmel's cultural theory in "The Conflict" is an expression of
that ambivalence.
18.
Just as his contemporary Unamuno (1954) was the agonist of Christianity,
Simmel is the agonist of modern culture. His agony cuts as deeply
as can be possibly imagined. His great sensitivity enabled or, perhaps,
condemned him to experience the spiritual currents of his time more profoundly
than his contemporaries did, and his brilliant intellect allowed or even
coerced him to express those currents with acute clarity. He was
the premier German philosopher of life in his generation, that is, he did
more than most others to propagate the rebellion of life, yet he understood
that the fate of life was to submit itself, even if only temporarily, to
its own products. An uncompromising will to truth prevented him from
seeking comfort in the aestheticism of dwelling in the exhausted forms,
but he also had to acknowledge the special or, as he called it, "peculiar,"
quality of form, its demand to constrain life. So, he could not embrace
the modernist rebellion against the principle of form, its normative autonomy.
And, further, he could not, like Emile Durkheim, take normative constraint
for granted as constitutive of actual culture because, somehow, it was
not. In his thought, just as in Unamuno's, lucidity bred agony and
paradox, from which he could not escape, but which he could express by
a strategic distancing in the form of cultural history and criticism.
19.
As Simmel turns in "The Conflict" to a fresh interpretation of the
currents of modernism which he had analyzed in "The Crisis" he breaks through
to the set of ideas that are associated with the contemporary rubric of
"deconstruction." His criticism is not itself deconstructionist -
it is a pure descriptive analysis - , but it details how the modernist
movements are themselves deconstructions of their objects or, better, of
the objectivity of their objects. The essence of modernism is the
deconstruction or de-objectivization of objectivized form; the attempt
to assimilate form to the process which generates it and to keep it there,
immanent to the process, so that it can never gain sufficient independence
to constrain creative expression. In general, modernist deconstruction
proceeds by the two-step process of rejecting the objectivity of form and
then of striving to make form an immanent function of life. Simmel's
ambivalence shows through in his description of the impulse to make form
subservient to form-giving life. In his discussions of expressionist
art, pragmatic and vitalist philosophy, and post-Christian piety he is
careful to affirm their intelligibility in terms of their positive vitality,
but he is equally concerned to show the problematicity of their rebellion
against the principle of form. His interpretation is an articulation,
an objectivization, of his ambivalence as a philosopher of life, a step,
therefore, beyond the modernist pretension and into a postmodernist acceptance
of broken form, failed mediation, and a subjectivity decentered by the
irreconcilable motives that constitute it. As he wrote in concluding
"The Crisis," cultural conflict is "consciously or not, the crisis of our
own soul."
20.
Simmel's ambivalence appears clearly in his interpretation of expressionist
art, which, unlike his treatment of it in "The Crisis," is sensitive and
even approving when it is contrasted to impressionism, which retains the
immediately perceived datum as an objective model. Expressionism
performs its deconstruction of objectivized forms of art by taking seriously
"the insight that a cause and its effect can have wholly dissimilar external
manifestations, that the dynamic relationship between them is purely internal
and need not produce any visual affinity."(Simmel, 1976b:230) The
expressionist artist "replaces the 'model' by the 'occasion,'" translating
the impulse awakened in him by a datum into a representation rather than
attempting to communicate the significance of the datum for itself.
Although the product of expressionist art is necessarily a form it does
not have the conventional work of art's "significance in itself," which
requires "creative life merely as the basis of its actualization."
Instead, the expressionist's form is an "unavoidable extraneous appendage"
of the form-giving process: form is present, but it has been deconstructed,
deprived of independence from creativity and, therefore, of regulatory
authority over it - it is a by-product of the function of expressivity.
The positivity of vital impulse here gains a triumph, but at a severe cost:
"Life, anxious only to express itself, has, as it were, jealously withheld
... meaning from its product." (Simmel, 1976b:230)
21.
The same pattern appears in such currents of post-metaphysical philosophy
as pragmatism and vitalism. In this phase of his discussion Simmel
replaces his reflection in "The Crisis" on the exhaustion of classical
metaphysical categories with a positive account of the deconstruction of
what Jacques Derrida (1974) calls the "metaphysics of presence," the description
of a realm of objective truth which the knower must acknowledge and seek
to discover. Pragmatism, according to Simmel, denies "the independence
of truth" by interpreting the object of knowledge not as a descriptor of
an autonomous reality but as an imagined idea which is called true if it
supports vital demands and false if it does not. The pragmatic philosopher
carries out the same sort of procedure of de-objectivization as the expressionist
artist, holding that "our ideas are dependent on our mental make-up, they
are by no means a mechanical reflection of the reality with which our practical
life is interwoven."(Simmel, 1976b:234) There is, then, "no independent,
pre-existent truth which is merely later incorporated, as it were, into
the stream of life in order to guide its course." Instead, life seeks
to guide itself through an imagination disciplined by the consequences
of its hypotheses: it reasserts "its sovereignty over a sphere which
hitherto appeared to be separate and independent of it." Here Simmel
does not even enter a reservation about the modernist impulse to deconstruct
objectivized form and to engender forms which are fully immanent functions
of its own vital dynamic. Indeed, his own philosophical doctrine
of the objectification of life into form was a contribution to modernism,
differing from the pragmatic interpretation mainly in its insistence on
the "peculiar" autonomous imperative of form and not on any independent
realm of truth.
22.
Simmel concludes his interpretation of modernist tendencies with a
reflection on post-Christian piety, which also displays a deconstructionist
impulse, this time aimed at any articles or doctrines of faith which would
command the believer's assent. Here the deconstruction proceeds even
more radically than it did in the cases of expressionism and pragmatism,
to the point at which life would "itself produce the sense of absolute
value which, in the past, appeared to be derived from the specific forms
of religious life, the particular articles of faith in which it had crystallized."(Simmel,
1976b:238) Religious modernism seeks to make faith an "intransitive
concept;" it is life seeking to produce out of itself "that unique inner
blend of humility and exaltation, tension and peace, vulnerability and
consecration, which we can describe in no other way than as religious."(Simmel,
1976b:238) Simmel shrinks from the implication of this tendency,
which is simply narcissism, the self-worship of life. At the only
point in "The Conflict" at which he retreats to the interregnum thinking
of "The Crisis" Simmel(1976b:239) doubts "whether a fundamental religious
need does not inevitably require an object ..., whether this is not merely
an interlude of an ideal nature which can never become reality, the symptom
of a situation where existing religious forms are being repudiated by the
inner religious life, which is, however, unable to replace them with new
ones." Religious modernism poses such a challenge to Simmel because for
him, as for Unamuno, a sentiment of life is at the core of religion and
there have always been mystics who have rejected its objectification into
imagery and doctrine. A mysticism of life, the final and radical
outcome of modernist deconstruction, would substitute immanent feeling
for transcendent meaning, putting into question the necessity of Simmel's
dialectical vision of the inevitable tension between life and form, the
need for life to confront itself as other to itself. It is just that
tension which is questioned and problematized by certain postmodern thinkers
who recur to Nietzsche. (Allison,1985) The conflict in modern culture
persists today, perhaps even more intensely than when Simmel wrote.
23.
Simmel ends "The Conflict" equivocally and far more soberly than he
did "The Crisis." No longer does he repose any trust in a "unified
dynamic" of life to heal even temporarily the modern agony, which is not
a struggle between two forms of culture but of life against what is deemed
to be its own inherent structure, an attempt of life to deconstruct itself.
In "The Crisis" he had suggested the most "perilous" project: "to
salvage the values of the former life and carry them over into the new
life." (Simmel, 1976a:260) At the end of "The Conflict" he
observes that "the link between the past and the future hardly ever seems
so completely shattered as at present, apparently leaving only intrinsically
formless life to bridge the gap."(Simmel, 1976b:241) But then he adds that
"it is equally certain that the movement is towards the typical evolution
of culture, the creation of new forms appropriate to present energies."
That has not happened in the generations since his death. Indeed,
those generations have witnessed ever renewed attempts of life to enslave
form. One need only think of the totalitarian rejections of the independence
of law and their milder counterparts in the industrialized democracies
to grasp the expansion of the rebellion against autonomous and demanding
form, or of mass entertainment in which life seeks an undemanding appreciation
of itself through the replication of its vanity. The rebellion of
life has become far more extensive since Simmel's time. Indeed, one
might conclude that autonomous form is not a need of the vital spirit but
one of its greatest goods, which must be self-consciously affirmed if it
is to exist at all.